Keywords
Filter, H-implicative almost distributive lattice, LI-ideals and implicative almost distributive lattice..
In this paper, we introduce the concept of H-implicative almost distributive lattices, which are a special class of lattices with both implicative and almost distributive properties. This study is aimed at extending the understanding of lattice structures and their ideals, particularly focusing on LI-ideals, a novel concept within H-implicative almost distributive lattices.
We define an LI-ideal of an implicative almost distributive lattice L and investigate its properties. The paper demonstrates that every LI-ideal in L is an almost distributive lattice ideal of L. Additionally, we explore the relationship between filters and LI-ideals, and we study the process of generating an LI-ideal from a given set. Lastly, we examine the construction of quotient structures via LI-ideals.
We present several examples showing that every almost distributive lattice ideal is also an LI-ideal in an H-implicative almost distributive lattice. The study establishes key relationships between the concepts of filters and LI-ideals. Furthermore, we provide a method for generating an LI-ideal from a set and construct a quotient structure using an LI-ideal.
The paper introduces new concepts and relationships within the study of H-implicative almost distributive lattices. Our findings demonstrate the interconnection between almost distributive lattice ideals and LI-ideals and offer insights into how these ideals can be generated and used to construct quotient structures. This work provides a deeper understanding of lattice theory and opens new avenues for further research in the area of lattice ideals.
Filter, H-implicative almost distributive lattice, LI-ideals and implicative almost distributive lattice..
In order to research the logical system whose propositional value is given in a lattice, Xu, Y.8 proposed the concept of lattice implication algebras and discussed some of their properties. Xu, Y. and Qin, K. Y.7 discussed the properties of lattice H-implication algebras. Jun, Y. B. and Xu, et al.3,9 introduced the notions of a filters in a lattice implication algebra and investigate their properties. Jun, Y. B. et al.4 proposed the concept of an LI-ideal of lattice implication algebra. They discussed the relationship between filters and LI-ideals and studied how to generate an LI-ideal by a set. They constructed quotient structure by using an LI-ideal. Kolluru,V. and Bekele, B.5the concept of implicative algebras was introduced, and several key properties were established. It was also proven that every implicative algebra is lattice implication algebra. In 1981, Swamy, U. M., and Rao, G. C. introduced the concept of an almost distributive lattice (ADL) as a common abstraction for many of the existing lattice structure.6
The existing ring-theoretic and lattice-theoretic generalizations of Boolean algebra have been explored in various studies. Berhanu Assaye, Mihret Alamneh, and Tilahun Mekonnen1 introduced the concept of implicative almost distributive lattices (IADLs) as a generalization of implicative algebras within the class of almost distributive lattices (ADLs). In this paper, we prove several properties and equivalence conditions within the framework of IADLs.
We also introduced filter, implicative filter in IADL.2 In this paper we discuss H-implicative almost distributive lattice (in short, H-IADL) and give equivalent conditions. We introduce LI-ideals in IADL and show that every LI-ideal is an ADL ideal. We give an example that an ADL ideal may not be an LI-ideal, and show that every ADL ideal is an LI-ideal in H-IADL. We discuss the relationship between filters and LI-ideal, and study how to generate an LI-ideal by a set. We construct quotient structure by using an LI-ideal.
In the following, we give some important definitions and results that will be useful in this study.
6 An algebra of type is called an almost distributive lattice (ADL) with if it satisfies the following axioms:
If (L, ∨, ∧, 0) is an ADL, for any , define if and only if or equivalently , then is a partial ordering on L.
6 Let L be an ADL. An element is called maximal if for any , implies
6 A non-empty subset I of an ADL L is called an ideal of L, if it satisfies the following:
The following important property of the ideals is very useful to develop the algebra of ideals. If I is an ideal of ADL L and , then if and only if
6 Let L be an ADL. For any , principal filter of L generated by a is
[6] A non-empty subset F of an ADL L is called a filter of L if it satisfies the following:
6 Let F is filter of an ADL L and . Then if and only if
6 Every ideal (filter) of L is a sub ADL of ADL L.
5 An algebra of type is called implicative algebra if it satisfies the following conditions:
5 Let be an implicative algebra. Then is a lattice implication algebra.
1 Let be an ADL with and maximal element m. Then an algebra of type is called implicative almost distributive lattice (IADL) if it satisfies the following conditions:
Now we define the relation on an IADL L as follows: , for all . The relation on L is a partial ordering.Thus is a poset.
1 In an IADL L, for all the following conditions hold:
2 Let L be an IADL.
2 Let F be a non-empty subset of an IADL L. Then F is a filter of L if and only if it satisfies for all and :
implies
2 Every filter F of an IADL L has the following property: and implies .
7 A lattice implication algebra L is called a lattice H-implication algebra, if for any , .
7 Let L be a lattice H-implication algebra. Then for any ,
1 Let L be an IADL, then for any , .
4 Let L be a lattice implication algebra. An LI-ideal A of L is a non-empty subset of L such that
4 In lattice H-implication algebra, every lattice ideal is an LI-ideal.
6 An ADL is said to be associative if the operation in L is associative.
6 An equivalence relation θ on an ADL L is called a congruence relation on L if for all , implies .
In this section first we introduce H-implicative almost distributive lattice (H-IADL). Then we introduce LI-ideals in IADLs and discuss some of their properties. Finally, we give some characterizations of LI-ideals.
In this subsection we introduce H-implicative almost distributive lattice (H-IADL) and study the conditions of IADL being H-IADL.
An implicative almost distributive lattice (IADL) L is called H-implicative almost distributive lattice (H-IADL) if it satisfies:
Let be a set. Define the partially ordered relation on L as and also define for all . Define the unary operation ′ and binary operation as shown in the tables below respectively.
Then clearly is an IADL and hence it can be easily verified that L is an H-IADL.
In the following some properties of H-IADLs are discussed.
Let L be an H-IADL. Then for any .
Let L be an H-IADL and . Now (by Definition 3.1 and Theorem 2.12). Therefore (1).
On the other hand, .
Therefore, Hence by (1) and (2), we get . □
Let L be an IADL. Then the following are equivalent:
Suppose . By assumption and Theorem 2.12,
(4) ⇒ (3). Suppose Now
Suppose (by Theorem 3.3).
Suppose . Therefore . Hence (5) holds.
. Suppose Then using Theorem 2.12 and Definition 3.1, = . Therefore, L is an H-IADL. □
An IADL is said to be associative IADL if in L is assocative
Let L be an associative IADL. Then the following statements are equivalent.
Let L be an IADL and .
). Suppose L is an H-IADL. Let z ∈ [x, m]. Then we have . From Theorem 2.12, we have This implies again (by Theorem 2.12 and Corollary 3.4), i.e., . Therefore (2) holds.
Putting z = x, we have x → (x → y) = x → y. Then it follows from Corollary 3.4 that L is an H-IADL.
Suppose . It follows that but we know from Theorem 2.12 that . Therefore it follows from Corollary 3.4 that L is an H-IADL.
Suppose L is an H-IADL. Using Corollary 3.4 and Theorem 2.12, we have ((x → y) → x) → x = (x → (x → y)) → (x → y) = (x → y) → (x → y) = m. Therefore and clearly . This implies Hence .
Suppose . Now (by supposition), it follows . That is (4) holds.
Suppose . Then . Therefore L is complemented IADL. Hence is associative. Now using Theorem 2.12 and our assumption we get (by Theorem 3.3). Hence It follows that , that is (3) holds. □
Let L be an H-IADL. Then for any
Let L be an H-IADL and . Now . This implies . Therefore, …(1). Conversely . This implies .... (2). Hence by (1) and (2), we have . □
In this section we introduce LI-ideal in IADL. We discuss some characterization of LI-ideal with that of H-IADL. We observe relation between LI-ideal and filters in IADL, construction of LI-ideal using a set and lastly we discuss quotient structure of LI-ideal in IADL.
Let L be an IADL. An LI-ideal A of L is a subset of L such that
(I1) and
(I2) implies that .
In this case if ,then A is proper LI-ideal of L. A proper LI-ideal A of L is said to be maximal if it is not properly contained in any other proper LI-ideal of L. That is, if I is any other LI-ideal of L such that implies either or , then A is maximal LI-ideal of L.
From the above definition we observe that {0} and L are trivial examples of LI-ideals.
The following example shows that there is a proper LI-ideal in IADL.
Let be the underlining set with partial ordering . Define the unary operation ′ and binary operation as shown in the tables below respectively.
–→ | 0 | x | y | z | w | m |
0 | m | m | m | m | m | m |
x | z | m | y | z | y | m |
y | w | x | m | y | x | m |
z | x | x | m | m | x | m |
w | y | m | m | y | m | m |
m | 0 | x | y | z | w | m |
Define the binary operation and by for all . Then clearly is an IADL. We can easily verify that is an LI-ideal of L.
Let A be an LI-ideal of IADL L. If and for some , then .
Let A be an LI-ideal of IADL L. Suppose and for some
Claim: for some . Since implies then by definition of LI-ideal (I2) we have . □
Let A be a non-empty subset of IADL L. Then A is an LI-ideal of L if and only if it satisfies for all and implies .
Suppose that A is an LI-ideal and . If , then by Theorem 3.11. Using definition 3.8 (I2) we obtain . Conversely, suppose that for all and implies . Since A is a non empty subset of L, we assume . Because , we have , and so I1 holds for A. Let and . Since ′, we have and so (I2) holds for A. Hence, A is an LI-ideal of L. □
Let L be an IADL. Every LI-ideal of L is an ADL ideal of L.
Let A be an LI-ideal of IADL L.
i. Let . Claim: .
Now (since . This implies (by Theorem 3.11). Thus (by Definition 3.8 (I2)).
ii. Suppose and
Claim: .
Now . This implies . Hence, from (i) and (ii) A is an ADL ideal of L. □
The converse of Theorem 3.13 is not true. Consider Example 3.10. The set A = {0, w} is an ADL ideal. But it is not an LI-ideal since and . □
Now we have the following characterization.
In H-IADL L, every ADL ideal is an LI-ideal.
Let and A be an ADL ideal of H-IADL L. Assume that and . We want to show that . Clearly . From Corollary 3.7, we have ′. Then it follows from Definition 2.3 (ii) that . Since , then we have . Hence A is an LI-ideal of L. □
Let A be a non empty subset of H-IADL L. Then A is an LI-ideal of L if and only if for every if and only if .
Suppose A is an LI-ideal of H-IADL L. Let . Since and A is an LI-ideal, then we have . Also implies as A is an LI-ideal. Conversely suppose if and only if and trivially . Hence, A is an LI-ideal.
For any A and B of IADL L we set A ∧ B = {a ∧ b|a ∈ A and b ∈ B}.
If A and B are LI-ideals of an H-IADL of L, then so is .
Let A and B be two LI-ideals of H-IADL L. Let . Then x = a1 ∧ b1 for a1 ∈ A and b1 ∈ B and y = a2 ∧ b2 for a2 ∈ A and b2 ∈ B. Now x ∨ y = (a1 ∧ b1) ∨ (a2 ∧ b2) = ((a1 ∧ b1) ∨ a2) ∧ ((a1 ∧ b1) ∨ b2) ∈ A ∧ B as ((a1 ∧ b1) ∨ a2 ∈ A . Then for some and . We observe that implies . Similarly one can show that and that and . Thus Hence, is an LI-ideal of L. □
If A and B are LI-ideals of an H-IADL L, then .
Let . Then for some and . Since implies (as A is an ADL ideal by Theorem 3.15 and properties of ideal in ADL) and , then from Theorem 3.11, and also and hence . Therefore, . Conversely suppose then . Therefore, . Hence, . □
If A is an LI-ideal of an H-IADL L and , then the set is an LI-idel of L.
Let . Then and . Using Theorem 2.13 that (by Theorem 3.24) so that . Conversely let be such that . Then . Using Theorem 2.12 and Theorem 3.3, we Thus which implies that and because A is an LI-ideal of H-IADL and Lemma 3.16. This implies that and . Hence by Theorem 2.13, K is an LI-ideal of L.
Let L be an H-IADL and .Then there is no proper LI-ideal of L containing and simultaneously.
Let A be a proper LI-ideal of H-IADL L containing a and a′ simultaneously. Then , and hence a contradiction. Therefore, A is not a proper LI-ideal of H-IADL L containing a and a′ simultaneously. □
For any non-empty subset A of an IADL L, we define . It is obvious that every non empty subset A of IADL L is not a filter. Similarly the set A′ for every subset A of L is not an LI-ideal in general. In fact the dual concept of a filter is one of an LI-ideal in IADL. Then we have the following theorem to verify this ideal.
Let A be a non empty subset of IADL L. Then A is a filter of L if and only if A′ is an LI-ideal of L.
Assume that A is a filter of IADL L. Then , and so Let ′ and ′ for all . Then and ′ for some . Thus . Since A is a filter, we have and so . This proves that A′ is an LI-ideal of L. Conversely let be such that and . We want to show . Suppose that A′ is an LI-ideal of L. Then and ′. As A′ is an LI-ideal, it follows from Definition 3.8 (I2) that or . Also . Hence, A is a filter of L. □
Suppose { i for index set J is a non-empty family of LI-ideal of IADL L. Then ∈J i is also an LI-ideal of L, for any of index set J.
Let i i
We need to show A = ∩i∈J Bi is also an LI-ideal of L.
1. Clearly i for each . This implies i∈J i
2. Since i and i i y ∈ ∩ i∈J B i implies i∈J i.
Therefore, A = ∩ i∈J B i is an LI-ideal of L.□
Let A be a subset of an IADL L. Then the least LI-ideal containing A is called the LI-ideal generated by A, written From Remark 3.14, L is clearly an LI- ideal Containing A. If is written In short we shall write [a1, a2, a3, · · ·, a n, x] for a1 → (a2 → (· · · → (a n → x) · · ·), and write [an, x] if a1 = a2 = · · · = an = a. So in our case we define m for some a1, · · ·, a n ∈ A} and n
For any natural number n we define n(x) → y recursively as follows: 1(x) → y = x → y and (n + 1)(x) → y = x → (n(x) → y).
Using definition 2.11(3) repeatedly, we know that the following identity in IADL holds:
In the following theorem we can describe elements of
If A is a non-empty subset of an IADL L, then = {x ∈ L|a1′→ → x′) · · ·) = m for some a1, · · ·, an is the least LI-idea of L containing.
Let us denote U = {x ∈ L | → (· · · ( a1′→ x′) · · ·) = m for some a1, · · ·, n }. We claim That is, we need to prove 1) , 2) is an LI-ideal, 3) for any LI-ideal V containing A. To prove (1). Since A is non-empty there exists such . This is implies a ∈1U. Therefore, . To prove 2) For implies . Let and , then there exists i and j ( j = 1, 2, 3, · · ·, p) such that a′ → (· · · (a′ → ((x → y)′)′ · · ·) = m…(
→ (· · · ( → y′) · · ·) = m…( From ( we have → (· · · (a′ →((y′ → x′) · · ·) = m … ( This implies y′ ≤ → (· · ·(a1′→ x′) · · ·) … (
Combining ( ( and properties of IADL, we get m = → (· · · ( →y′) · · ·) ≤ → (· · ·( →→ (· · ·( → x′) · · ·))) · · ·) and hence →(· · · ( →( → (·· · (a′→ x′) · · ·))) · · ·) = m. This shows that .
Therefore, U is an LI-ideal of L containing A. To prove 3) Let V be an LI- ideal containing A and let . Then ( → (· · ·( → x′) · · ·) = m for some 1 n . Thus m = ( →(( → (· · · ( → x′) · · ·))= ( →(( → (· · · ( → x′) · · ·))) = ( → → (· · )· ·))→an, which implies that (( → (· · · ( → x′) · · ·))′ → an)′ = m′ = .
Since n and V is an LI-ideal of L, we have ( → (· · · ( →x′) · · · . Now ( → (· · · ( → x′) · · ·))′ = ( → (· · · ( → x′) → a n−1) · · ·))′, since , it follows from Definition 3.16 I2 that ( → (· · · (a′→ x′) · · · . Repeating the process we conclude that and . As V is an LI-ideal of L we have . This proves that , hence That is, U is the least LI-ideal containing A. □
The following corollary is immediate from Theorem 3.23.
For any element a of an IADL L, we have m for some natural number n}.
Let A be an an LI-ideal of IADL L and . Then
Let A be an LI-ideal of IADL L and . Consider a . Since , then a. Let a and a. Then there exist such that and . It follows that and for some , so that and Then Using Theorem 2.12 . Since , it follows from Theorem 3.23 that . Hence and Aa is LI-ideal of L. Since , then a. Let . Since , it follows from Theorem 3.19 that i.e., a and so a. Thus a. Finally we show that Aa is the least LI-ideal containing A and a. Let B be any LI-ideal containing A and a, and let a. Then for some , and hence . Since it follows from definition of LI-ideal we have . Repeating this process we obtain . Therefore, Aa is the least LI- ideal containing Aa and a, i.e., a.
Let L be an IADL and .If and for some , then there exists such that
Let A be an LI-ideal of an IADL L. Then for all .
Let By Theorem 3.23, there are such that and . Hence (n(a′) → x′)′ = u and (m(b′) → x′)′ = v for some . It follows that and so that and . Using Lemma 3.26, there exists such that . Since we have Applying Theorem 3.21 we get by Theorem 3.23. Thus, . Conversely if then for some . Since , then Using Theorem 2.12(10) repeatedly, we get , which imply that and Applying Theorem 3.19, we get and , i.e., and . Hence, and so . □
Let A be an LI-ideal of IADL L. We define a binary relation “ ” on L as follows: if and only if and for all .
The binary relation “∼” on IADL L is an equivalent relation on L.
Let L be an IADL L such that and A be an LI-ideal of L. Then
1. . This implies is reflexive on L.
2. and if and only if and if and only if . Therefore is symmetric on L.
3. Assume and . We need to show that . Now and implies and and . Since it follows from Theorem 3.19 that . Since and A is LI-ideal of L, we have .
Similarly, it also follows from Theorem 3.19 that . Therefore . Hence is transitive on L. □
If and in an LI-ideal A of IADL L, then for any .
Let L be an IADL and . Assume that and of an LI-ideal A. Then and and . Since and , it follows from Theorem 3.19 that and . This implies that Similarly Since and , it follows from Theorem 3.19 that and . This implies …(2). From (1), (2) and transitivity of , We conclude that . □
Let for an LI-ideal A of IADL L. Assume and . Then
The binary relation is a congruence relation on an IADL L.
Using Lemma 3.28, Proposition 3.29 and Corollary 3.30, it is clear that ~ is a congruence relation on L. □
Now we have the following definition. Let A be an LI-ideal of IADL L. Then the equivalent class containing x is denoted by Ax such that and the set of all equivalent classes of L is denoted by such that
A0 = A and m .
and for all implies . This implies 0. Therefore 0. Conversely, 0 and and . Therefore, . Hence, A0 = A.
m and □
Define binary operations “∪”, “∩”, “⇒” and unary operation “N” on as follows:
Then we have the following lemma.
Let L be an IADL and A be an LI-ideal of L. Then
Let L be an IADL and A be an LI-ideal of L. Let x y z for all . Then
1. Since 0 x 0∨x x and 0 x 0∧x 0, for all . This implies A0 is the least element of L|A. Also m x m∨x m and m x m∧x x, for all . This implies A m is the greatest element of L|A. Therefore, 0 m is bounded. we can easily verify that 0 m is an ADL.
2. To show 0 m is an IADL,
(a) x y x∨y (x→y)→y x y y
(b) (x→y)→x′ = [(Ax ⇒ Ay) ⇒ AN]xN
(c) x y z Ax→(y→z) y→(x→z) y x z
(d) m x m→x x
(e) x m x→m m
(f ) x y x→y y′→x′ y′ x′ yN xN
(g) = A0′ = Am
Therefore, 0 m is quotient IADL. □
Many scholars investigated ideals in lattice and ADL. Furthermore, LI-ideals in Lattice implication algebras are discussed by different researchers. For the advancement of many valued logical algebra we extend this notion to ADL concept. That is, first we investigated H-implicative almost distributive lattice. Then we discussed LI-ideals in IADL. Lastly, we found an interesting result that set theoretic LI-ideals is an LI-ideal and some characterization of LI-ideals in IADL. In the future we will have fuzzy version of this notion.
All the authors are contributed equally in this manuscript and also both authors read and approved the final manuscript.
Views | Downloads | |
---|---|---|
F1000Research | - | - |
PubMed Central
Data from PMC are received and updated monthly.
|
- | - |
Is the work clearly and accurately presented and does it cite the current literature?
Partly
Is the study design appropriate and is the work technically sound?
Yes
Are sufficient details of methods and analysis provided to allow replication by others?
No
If applicable, is the statistical analysis and its interpretation appropriate?
I cannot comment. A qualified statistician is required.
Are all the source data underlying the results available to ensure full reproducibility?
No source data required
Are the conclusions drawn adequately supported by the results?
Yes
Competing Interests: No competing interests were disclosed.
Reviewer Expertise: logical algebras
Alongside their report, reviewers assign a status to the article:
Invited Reviewers | |
---|---|
1 | |
Version 1 10 Feb 25 |
read |
Provide sufficient details of any financial or non-financial competing interests to enable users to assess whether your comments might lead a reasonable person to question your impartiality. Consider the following examples, but note that this is not an exhaustive list:
Sign up for content alerts and receive a weekly or monthly email with all newly published articles
Already registered? Sign in
The email address should be the one you originally registered with F1000.
You registered with F1000 via Google, so we cannot reset your password.
To sign in, please click here.
If you still need help with your Google account password, please click here.
You registered with F1000 via Facebook, so we cannot reset your password.
To sign in, please click here.
If you still need help with your Facebook account password, please click here.
If your email address is registered with us, we will email you instructions to reset your password.
If you think you should have received this email but it has not arrived, please check your spam filters and/or contact for further assistance.
Comments on this article Comments (0)