ALL Metrics
-
Views
-
Downloads
Get PDF
Get XML
Cite
Export
Track
Opinion Article

Moral injury and the four pillars of bioethics

[version 1; peer review: 2 approved with reservations]
PUBLISHED 26 Jul 2019
Author details Author details
OPEN PEER REVIEW
REVIEWER STATUS

Abstract

Health care providers experience moral injury when their internal ethics are violated. The routine and direct exposure to ethical violations makes clinicians particularly vulnerable to harm. The fundamental ethics in health care typically fall into the four broad categories of patient autonomy, beneficence, nonmaleficence, and social justice. Patients have a moral right to determine their own goals of medical care, that is, they have autonomy. When this principle is violated, moral injury occurs. Beneficence is the desire to help people, so when the delivery of proper medical care is obstructed for any reason, moral injury is the result. Nonmaleficence, meaning do no harm, has been a primary principle of medical ethics throughout recorded history. Yet today, even the most advanced and safest medical treatments all are associated with unavoidable, harmful side-effects. When an inevitable side-effect occurs, not only is the patient harmed, the clinician also suffers a moral injury. Social injustice results when patients experience suboptimal treatment due to their race, gender, religion, or other demographic variables. While moral injury occurs routinely in medical care and cannot be entirely eliminated, clinicians can decrease the prevalence of injury by advocating for the ethical treatment of patients, not only at the bedside, but also by addressing the ethics of political influence, governmental mandates, and administrative burdens on the delivery of optimal medical care. Although clinicians can strengthen their resistance to moral injury by deepening their own spiritual foundation, that is not enough. Improvements in the ethics of the healthcare system as a whole are necessary in order to improve medical care and decrease moral injury.

Keywords

moral injury, burnout, bioethics

Introduction

Moral injury occurs when a person experiences an immoral event that disrupts their fundamental moral integrity. Injuries can be self-inflicted by intentionally doing something wrong or come about as collateral damage through observation of a real or perceived action that violates an internal sense of right and wrong. Those suffering from moral injury have a disruption of their sense of morality, with consequences impacting their capacity to behave in a moral manner. The injury reduces their capacity to think of themselves as a moral, good person (Yan, 2016).

The term moral injury was introduced initially to describe the reaction of military veterans to the participation in or observation of profound ethical transgressions occurring during wartime (Shay & Munroe, 1999). The diagnosis of moral injury in veterans relies on the presence of three factors: a betrayal of what is right, which is carried out by someone who holds legitimate authority (e.g. a leader), and occurs in a high stakes situation (Shay, 2014). The diagnosis of moral injury, however, has not been limited to those exposed to the atrocities of war. It has also been evaluated in refugees, health care workers, and adolescents transitioning to adults (Chaplo et al., 2019). In these diverse groups, while moral injury is recognized as a distinct entity from other psychological conditions, such as post-traumatic stress disorder, the diagnosis relies on poorly defined, generalized criteria, which is very similar to that used for combat veterans. While symptom scales have been developed for military personnel, adolescents, and refugees, no specific diagnostic criteria exist for health care workers (Chaplo et al., 2019; Koenig et al., 2018; Nickerson et al., 2018).

The optimal treatment of moral injury, just like the diagnosis of moral injury, remains unclear. Proposals to treat moral injury in medical professionals include participation in support groups, building up personal character, and personal reflection by keeping a diary. The inclusion of standard treatments for post-traumatic stress disorder in veterans suffering from moral injury has also been proposed.

A maxim of medicine is that a correct diagnosis is half the cure. In the case of moral injury as it specifically applies to medical professionals, we propose that a violation of the four pillars of bioethics forms the foundation of the diagnosis. We propose a framework for moral injury in health care based upon the four pillars of bioethics (Beauchamp, 2006). These pillars are patient autonomy, beneficence, nonmaleficence, and social justice. They serve as an effective foundation for evaluating moral behavior in medicine. Our framework clarifies the meaning of moral injury in medicine. When a physician, nurse, or other health care provider participates in, or witnesses a violation of, one or more of these core principles, moral injury occurs. Treatment strategies focused on repairing the breach of these principles of morality in health care may be the best way to heal the injury. Improving the recognition of and reflection upon the moral stressors that clinicians encounter in their practice may prevent moral injury from progressing further. This framework will help more clearly define moral injury in medical professionals, allowing the development of treatment specific to those working in health care.

Patient autonomy

The principle of respect for autonomy holds that each person with capacity has the right to make their own decisions, and providers have a moral obligation to respect this right. In the clinician-patient relationship, patient autonomy can be especially vulnerable. This principle is often at the forefront of ethical concerns in health care (Entwistle et al., 2010); (Stammers, 2015).

Compromising patient autonomy can result in moral injury, regardless of whether or not the perceived event is a true violation. For example, children presenting to the emergency department may openly voice a desire to not get an injection or an intravenous line. Although it is recognized that the decision of the legal caregiver overrides that of a young child, the perception of compromised autonomy can result in moral injury. Although the reason for the injection or intravenous line is medically indicated, the action nevertheless is against the will of the child. Logically, we know children will cry and object to many medical treatments. Still, whenever possible, it is recommended to obtain consent from both the child and the parent. Consent to treatment requires permission from the legal representative of the child, and if possible, assent from the child as well (Tait & Hutchinson, 2018). The accumulation of such experiences that challenge the clinician’s duty to respect patient autonomy may eventually lead to moral injury.

Nonmaleficence

The principle of nonmaleficence is captured by the Latin maxim, primum non nocere: “above all, do no harm.” It has been estimated that medical error is the third leading cause of death in the United States (Makary & Daniel, 2016). While the potential to reduce these errors is debated, common preventable harms include medication adverse events, central line infections, and thromboembolisms (Nabhan et al., 2012). With increasing ability to treat patients comes increasing opportunity to harm patients as systems become more complex. Most clinicians are very aware and regularly reminded of these statistics, however, the seemingly futile efforts to try and reduce the incidence of these harms is troublesome and can contribute to moral injury. Bureaucratic and administrative interference, well intended or not, can hamper efforts by physicians and nurses to decrease harm, leading to moral injury and a sense of powerlessness.

Beneficence

With the many opportunities to harm a patient in mind, we must also remember that patients come to clinicians in search of improvement or restoration of their health, which leads to the principle of beneficence. The commitment to helping others is the driving force amongst health care workers and to accomplish this goal there must be a net benefit over harm (Gillon, 1994). Decisions on diagnostic pathways, treatment plans and societal policies all must balance the benefit versus harms, and these balances also must be made in context of the patient’s values.

Beneficence, when compromised, creates numerous conflicts in medicine that can result in moral injury. When the cost of proper medical care exceeds the ability of an individual patient to pay, beneficence can be compromised. Pharmaceutical pricing is a common cause of this moral compromise. For example, many patients with atrial fibrillation will benefit from changing their warfarin prescription to a newer, direct oral anticoagulant such as apixaban. However, the up-front price of the newer medication prohibits them from changing, even though the total financial cost of the newer medication is estimated to be lower due to fewer medical complications (Gupta et al., 2018). Beyond the financial impact, the negative impact upon the patient’s health can be devastating. Compromising the principle of beneficence occurs when the patient is unable to take the best medication because of financial limitations. Although the medical complications from the older medication will ultimately cost more money, the hard reality is that patients will take the cheaper medication because they cannot afford the up-front costs of the newer, better medication.

Social justice

The final pillar of bioethics is social justice. Justice demands that limited resources be distributed fairly, and that patients not be discriminated against due to any number of demographic variables such as race, religion, gender identity, sexual orientation, age, or cultural background. Moral injury occurs when these ideals conflict with the hard reality of medical care where discrimination does occur, primarily along socioeconomic lines.

These complex socioeconomic disparities cause moral injury because clinicians know what their patients need and find the economic barriers to needed care to be illogical, unnecessary, and capricious. They know that not getting that nursing home bed placement will result in a bad outcome, often at a much higher cost. They know that not getting a patient with a substance use disorder necessary treatment will ultimately cost more to society, although the health care plan may save money. They have seen first-hand the elderly family member decide they would rather die than leave a large medical bill for their surviving relatives. Witnessing these events on a regular basis doesn’t cause burnout, it causes moral injury.

Medical professionals working in medical systems and countries that rely on privately funded insurance may also experience a constant violation of the principle of social justice. For example, one study comparing a population with universal medical insurance found disparities in the care given to racial and ethnic minorities to be greatly decreased or even eliminated (Chaudhary et al., 2018). A similar study found that universal medical insurance ameliorated socioeconomic disparities in mortality (Veugelers & Yip, 2003). Medical professionals working in private medical insurance systems who know about and trust such research studies may experience a persistent low-grade violation of their bioethics. This, over time, may progress to symptomatic moral injury. The primary means of addressing such issues would be meaningful involvement in improving the larger health care system.

Conclusion

Moral injury occurs when there is a disruption in an individual’s sense of personal morality and capacity to behave in a just manner. It is a common occurrence in medicine because of ongoing violations of bioethics that have become an intrinsic part of the healthcare system. The prevention of moral injury is accomplished by decreasing violations of the four pillars of bioethics whenever possible. Patients deserve autonomy, and we can give this to them. Although we cannot always help our patients as much as we would like, we can always help them in at least some way. We can be vigilant when taking measures to increase patient safety and decrease harm. With a firm understanding of the basic principles of bioethics, medical professionals can become more adept at identifying and reflecting upon moral violations in the workplace. This recognition helps prevent recurrent moral injury, decreases burnout, and can help to heal previous injuries.

Data availability

No data are associated with this article.

Comments on this article Comments (0)

Version 4
VERSION 4 PUBLISHED 26 Jul 2019
Comment
Author details Author details
Competing interests
Grant information
Copyright
Download
 
Export To
metrics
Views Downloads
F1000Research - -
PubMed Central
Data from PMC are received and updated monthly.
- -
Citations
CITE
how to cite this article
Heston TF and Pahang JA. Moral injury and the four pillars of bioethics [version 1; peer review: 2 approved with reservations]. F1000Research 2019, 8:1193 (https://doi.org/10.12688/f1000research.19754.1)
NOTE: If applicable, it is important to ensure the information in square brackets after the title is included in all citations of this article.
track
receive updates on this article
Track an article to receive email alerts on any updates to this article.

Open Peer Review

Current Reviewer Status: ?
Key to Reviewer Statuses VIEW
ApprovedThe paper is scientifically sound in its current form and only minor, if any, improvements are suggested
Approved with reservations A number of small changes, sometimes more significant revisions are required to address specific details and improve the papers academic merit.
Not approvedFundamental flaws in the paper seriously undermine the findings and conclusions
Version 1
VERSION 1
PUBLISHED 26 Jul 2019
Views
20
Cite
Reviewer Report 13 Jul 2020
Jan Helge Solbakk, Department of Health and Society, Centre for medical Ethics, University of Oslo, Oslo, Norway 
Approved with Reservations
VIEWS 20
This is a very short and well written paper. But the paper would have benefited from further substantiation by relating the concept of moral injury to the concepts of moral failure, moral residue and moral distress.

Here are ... Continue reading
CITE
CITE
HOW TO CITE THIS REPORT
Solbakk JH. Reviewer Report For: Moral injury and the four pillars of bioethics [version 1; peer review: 2 approved with reservations]. F1000Research 2019, 8:1193 (https://doi.org/10.5256/f1000research.21667.r65320)
NOTE: it is important to ensure the information in square brackets after the title is included in all citations of this article.
  • Author Response 17 Nov 2023
    Thomas F Heston, Washington State University, USA
    17 Nov 2023
    Author Response
    Thank you again for your time and effort in helping improve this article. I apologize for the delayed response, which was unavoidable due to a severe, prolonged illness. I believe ... Continue reading
COMMENTS ON THIS REPORT
  • Author Response 17 Nov 2023
    Thomas F Heston, Washington State University, USA
    17 Nov 2023
    Author Response
    Thank you again for your time and effort in helping improve this article. I apologize for the delayed response, which was unavoidable due to a severe, prolonged illness. I believe ... Continue reading
Views
47
Cite
Reviewer Report 26 Jul 2019
Lindsay B Carey, Department of Public Health, School of Psychology and Public Health, La Trobe University, Melbourne, Vic, Australia 
Approved with Reservations
VIEWS 47
This is an innovative and valuable consideration/discussion of moral injury (MI) in light of the key bioethical principles - both of which are used to justify the political issue of employee burnout within the clinical context.

Given ... Continue reading
CITE
CITE
HOW TO CITE THIS REPORT
Carey LB. Reviewer Report For: Moral injury and the four pillars of bioethics [version 1; peer review: 2 approved with reservations]. F1000Research 2019, 8:1193 (https://doi.org/10.5256/f1000research.21667.r51660)
NOTE: it is important to ensure the information in square brackets after the title is included in all citations of this article.
  • Author Response 13 Aug 2019
    Thomas F Heston, Washington State University, USA
    13 Aug 2019
    Author Response
    I appreciate the comments from the reviewer and in general agree. In other groups outside of health care providers, moral injury is becoming more precisely defined. However, the definition and ... Continue reading
  • Reviewer Response 29 Jul 2019
    Lindsay B Carey, Department of Public Health, School of Psychology and Public Health, La Trobe University, Melbourne, Australia
    29 Jul 2019
    Reviewer Response
    Dear Article Authors,

    I concur with your "aim to stimulate investigation into the relationship between a violation of well established bioethical principles and moral injury" and "that moral injury.... regularly affects ... Continue reading
  • Author Response 17 Nov 2023
    Thomas F Heston, Washington State University, USA
    17 Nov 2023
    Author Response
    Thank you again for your time and effort in helping improve this article. I apologize for the delayed response, which was unavoidable due to severe, prolonged illness. I believe this ... Continue reading
COMMENTS ON THIS REPORT
  • Author Response 13 Aug 2019
    Thomas F Heston, Washington State University, USA
    13 Aug 2019
    Author Response
    I appreciate the comments from the reviewer and in general agree. In other groups outside of health care providers, moral injury is becoming more precisely defined. However, the definition and ... Continue reading
  • Reviewer Response 29 Jul 2019
    Lindsay B Carey, Department of Public Health, School of Psychology and Public Health, La Trobe University, Melbourne, Australia
    29 Jul 2019
    Reviewer Response
    Dear Article Authors,

    I concur with your "aim to stimulate investigation into the relationship between a violation of well established bioethical principles and moral injury" and "that moral injury.... regularly affects ... Continue reading
  • Author Response 17 Nov 2023
    Thomas F Heston, Washington State University, USA
    17 Nov 2023
    Author Response
    Thank you again for your time and effort in helping improve this article. I apologize for the delayed response, which was unavoidable due to severe, prolonged illness. I believe this ... Continue reading

Comments on this article Comments (0)

Version 4
VERSION 4 PUBLISHED 26 Jul 2019
Comment
Alongside their report, reviewers assign a status to the article:
Approved - the paper is scientifically sound in its current form and only minor, if any, improvements are suggested
Approved with reservations - A number of small changes, sometimes more significant revisions are required to address specific details and improve the papers academic merit.
Not approved - fundamental flaws in the paper seriously undermine the findings and conclusions
Sign In
If you've forgotten your password, please enter your email address below and we'll send you instructions on how to reset your password.

The email address should be the one you originally registered with F1000.

Email address not valid, please try again

You registered with F1000 via Google, so we cannot reset your password.

To sign in, please click here.

If you still need help with your Google account password, please click here.

You registered with F1000 via Facebook, so we cannot reset your password.

To sign in, please click here.

If you still need help with your Facebook account password, please click here.

Code not correct, please try again
Email us for further assistance.
Server error, please try again.