Keywords
Big question, epistemic responsibilities, humanities, research integrity, societal relevance, teaching, university, virtue
This article is included in the Research on Research, Policy & Culture gateway.
Big question, epistemic responsibilities, humanities, research integrity, societal relevance, teaching, university, virtue
In this paper, we propose a normative taxonomy of what we call the ‘Big Five’ in academia: five core epistemic responsibilities of universities. Epistemic responsibilities are responsibilities that have to do with the attainment of knowledge, understanding, insight, rationality, and explanation. Thus, they are to be distinguished from moral responsibilities – that concern the well-being of humans and animals – and practical responsibilities, such as the responsibility to develop societally useful technologies and effective medical interventions1. For each epistemic responsibility, we distinguish five levels describing the extent to which a university meets that responsibility or strives to do so. Our taxonomy is meant as a tool to assess the degree to which a university meets its core epistemic responsibilities. The format we use is inspired by the Transparency and Openness Promotion (TOP) guidelines2 that journals can use to describe the extent to which they meet the goals of Open Science.
The taxonomy proposed here is a product of two research projects funded by the Templeton World Charity Foundation: Science beyond Scientism (2013–2016) and The Epistemic Responsibilities of the University (2016–2019)3. The first project explored which questions science can and which ones it cannot address, as well as whether the natural sciences are the only reliable source of knowledge. The second project explored what the core epistemic responsibilities of universities are, given various contemporary challenges, such as hypercompetition, publication pressure, the marginalization of the humanities, and the commercialization of the university. In both projects, philosophers worked in close cooperation with biomedical and social scientists. We present this as work in progress, as a starting point for gaining experience with using the taxonomy and consensus building for a more mature version.
This paper is structured as follows. First, we provide the taxonomy by specifying academia’s Big Five epistemic responsibilities and detailing five levels of meeting them (Table 1). After that, we argue that these are indeed five core epistemic responsibilities of universities (section 2). Finally, we lay out which future steps we aim to take to test, amend, and implement the taxonomy (section 3).
Our proposal distinguishes five epistemic responsibilities. We consider each to be of equal importance, so the order in which we present them is not hierarchical. The attainment levels I through V for each responsibility, however, are meant hierarchically: each level presents a more advanced stage of meeting the responsibility at issue.
We think of these responsibilities as attaching primarily to entire universities. So, in order to meet them, each responsibility should have systematic consequences, throughout the university and its faculties, departments, institutes, or other organizational parts. If a university strives to teach for intellectual virtue at the highest level, for example, students throughout the university should be instructed in what these virtues are and stimulated to cultivate them through virtue-building teaching activities.
This doesn’t mean that there cannot be an internal division of labour when it comes to meeting epistemic responsibilities: giving humanistic inquiry a proper place will primarily fall on humanities departments, although humanities scholars will teach in other departments and collaborate with scientists in other departments as well when a university strives for level V of this responsibility. Similarly, not all departments and research teams will have to serve society in the same way or to an equal degree. There will be significant differences between, say, the theoretical physicists and the nutrition scientists.
We will now clarify each responsibility briefly and motivate why it belongs on the list of epistemic responsibilities of universities.
1. To foster research integrity. Research integrity is fostered by getting rid of perverse incentives, stimulating good mentoring, having an open research climate, and so on. Detrimental research practices include both rare major research misbehaviours like fabrication of data and highly prevalent minor misbehaviours like selective reporting4. By ‘responsible conduct of research’ we mean behavior that meets the principles and standards for good research, as laid out in major codes of conduct for research integrity5. Such behavior can be stimulated at the level of individual scholars, but also that of groups, such as research teams or departments. Ideally, research integrity is promoted for both individuals and groups.
The results of scientific and scholarly research play a crucial role in modern society. Universities carry out a substantial part of this research and educate and train researchers who perform the studies and apply the results. To ensure the validity and trustworthiness of findings research needs to be performed according to the principles and standards for research integrity. In recent years it has become painfully evident that there is substantial room for improvement in the level of compliance to these principles and standards6. Surveys indicate that 2% of researchers admit to having fabricated or falsified data themselves, while one third says that they have been engaged in less serious questionable research practices7. Only 10 – 40% of study results turn out to be reproducible when the study is repeated8. This is due to small sample sizes, selective reporting and other questionable research practices. Although these phenomena are understudied, it is clear that more transparency9 and specifically preregistration10 of study protocols and data analysis plans will lead to considerable improvements. This epistemic responsibility entails not only the adoption of transparency and educating staff and students in responsible conduct of research, but also removing perverse incentives from the ways in which researchers are assessed11 and performing research on research to strengthen the evidence base for optimizing research integrity.
2. To teach for intellectual virtue. Among the intellectual virtues are: open-mindedness, attentiveness, charitableness, intellectual courage, creativity, curiosity, discernment, honesty, intellectual humility, objectivity, parsimony, perseverance, studiousness and wisdom12. Educating for intellectual virtues is part of the traditional ideal of Bildung. Moral virtues, such as generosity, kindness, or benevolence, may well also be important and universities might have a responsibility to cultivate them, but, if so, this isn’t an epistemic responsibility. When universities choose to teach for intellectual virtues, they can do so, minimally, by merely bringing up these virtues in educational settings; or they can explore them through case studies of intellectually virtuous scientists and scholars and their contributions to epistemic progress, or, most advanced, they can actively cultivate intellectual virtues in their students by having them mimic and practise intellectually virtuous behaviour. Developing intellectual virtues requires not merely instruction about virtues or reflection on them, but training and exercise13.
Teaching for intellectual virtues is a responsibility of universities almost by definition. Intellectual virtues are broadly understood as qualities that make someone a well-trained thinker or inquirer14. Hence, the two main tasks of universities, research and teaching, are both served by teaching for intellectual virtue. By aiming to train students to become skilled thinkers (perhaps among other things), universities set an ambitious goal for education. Similarly, academic research also needs skilled thinkers. Moreover, the intellectual virtues are widely relevant outside the university: in politics, journalism, medicine, law, law enforcement, social work – it’s hard to think of any sphere of life where good, analytical, critical, clearheaded, creative, or otherwise high quality thinking wouldn’t matter.
3. To address the big questions of life. By ‘the big questions’ we mean such questions as: What is the origin and ultimate destination of all that exists? What is the future of the earth’s ecosystem? What is consciousness? Do humans have free will? Is there (objective) good and evil? Can the human mind understand the world and, if so, how? Does life have meaning? Does God exist? How does science relate to religion? These are universal questions in the sense that they have been asked in most cultures and societies throughout history, up to the present; they are not restricted to local concerns or specific academic disciplines.
Addressing the big questions of life is an epistemic responsibility of the university for a number of reasons. First, these questions are too important to be left entirely to non-academics. Second, many academics themselves are greatly interested in these questions, even if their specialized science and scholarship does not or even cannot answer them. Third, clarifying and attempting to answer these questions affects how we look at ourselves and what we deem important. Fourth, several big questions are factual questions – highly abstract and large scale, but factual nonetheless. They are not questions about tastes or preferences. They seem to admit of true or false answers. So, at least in principle, they fall within the purview of scientific and humanistic inquiry. Fifth, big questions can inspire smaller and more manageable research questions. For example, asking about the fundamental nature of reality led to the hypothesis of atomism in Ancient Greece15. Ideas about God’s perfection and omnipotence led Galileo to assume that mathematics is our best guide to understanding the orbits of the planets and hence that heliocentrism rather than geocentrism is correct16. Darwin asked whether humans are unique or whether all life on earth is monogenetic, which led him to develop evolutionary theory17. Einstein opposed the Copenhagen interpretation of quantum mechanics on metaphysical grounds, as he didn’t believe the universe could be fundamentally probabilistic18. For these reasons universities cannot and should not operate as if the big questions don’t exist or cannot be taken seriously. Rather, they should take them seriously and mobilize their intelligence as well as state of the art science and scholarship to address these questions in an intellectually responsible way.
4. To give humanistic inquiry and education a proper place. Universities ought to have room for the full range of academic disciplines, in both the sciences and the humanities. Many of today’s most urgent challenges in society cannot be solved by purely scientific or technological means; successful solutions require compelling communication, consideration of moral values and norms, and in-depth understanding of cultures and religions. All of these things, and much more, are studied in the humanities. Hence, universities ought to facilitate and embrace humanistic inquiry and teaching, and stimulate interdisciplinary collaborations between scientists and humanities scholars. Of course, some universities – technological universities, for instance – do not include humanities departments. For them, this responsibility may be either left aside, or be interpreted as follows: the responsibility to give due weight to knowledge and understanding produced by humanities departments in other universities.
Giving the humanities a proper place is a responsibility of the university for one basic reason: the humanities can deliver truth, knowledge and insight in areas where the sciences cannot19. The humanities have their own objects of study: they study objects that have “meaning” in a special sense, viz. meaning that derives from human conventions, from human intentions, and/or from human purposive behaviour20. The knowledge and understanding the humanities provide differs from the knowledge and understanding that the sciences offer, in that the former is often ‘indexical’ (that is, related to human interests and concerns), ‘perspectival’ (it specifies how things look from, say, a romantic perspective), and value-related (that is, related to social, political, moral, aesthetic, or religious values)21. In addition to this, the humanities are particularly suitable for educating students to become well-informed, critical citizens who can reflect on socially urgent questions about life, health, education, justice, equality, liberty, etc. and participate fully in society and politics22.
5. To serve society. Universities can serve society at a number of levels: local (a city or region), national, or international, humanity worldwide. What we have in mind here is serving society epistemically, that is, to help society acquire true belief, knowledge, and understanding about important issues. So, what we have in mind are such things as press releases, expert advice, popular articles, opinion pieces, public lectures, interviews, and so on. Of course, universities sometimes also serve society in a more practical manner, e.g., by way of proposing effective policies, producing medical interventions and other technologies. Such practical interventions are often based on scientific evidence, so the epistemic and the practical are not entirely separate, but they can be distinguished for analytical purposes. We focus on the former here, as our taxonomy concerns the epistemic rather than the moral, practical, or social responsibilities of universities.
This is a responsibility for at least two reasons. First, many scientific and scholarly discoveries are so complex that if academics do not disseminate their knowledge, those discoveries will remain unknown among the larger audience. Second, it often requires extensive academic knowledge to understand the importance and ramifications of various discoveries. Knowledge and understanding are of intrinsic epistemic value. If the university does not serve society by sharing academic knowledge and understanding, then, for much academic knowledge and understanding, that value will be attained only by a very small group of academics in the relevant field. If the university takes its epistemic responsibility of knowledge dissemination seriously, then much larger groups – academics in other fields, society as a whole – will attain those epistemic values.
As indicated, we propose our normative taxonomy as a tool to assess the degree to which a university meets the Big Five epistemic responsibilities. Our proposal is a first attempt; in future work we aim to validate, test, amend, and implement the taxonomy. We envision doing this in four consecutive steps.
First, we want to fine-tune our taxonomy in a Delphi Study23,24 with international experts that aims in its first round at adding, replacing, and reformulating various epistemic responsibilities. The second and third Delphi rounds will seek consensus on the corresponding levels of meeting the responsibility at issue and explore what the best practices are for reaching higher levels of specific responsibilities.
Next, we will organize co-creation workshops25 with representatives of relevant stakeholders in order to discuss a penultimate version of the taxonomy. The focus of the workshop will be on the operationalization of the levels of meeting the different epistemic responsibilities in a way which makes application of the taxonomy feasible, transparent, and as objective as possible.
Then, we will test and qualitatively evaluate the taxonomy in a number of universities, resulting in a definitive description of the responsibilities, the levels, and a toolkit of best practices.
Finally, we will publish and disseminate the results on a dedicated website and explore whether the taxonomy is a suitable alternative for, or addition to, the currently dominant Academic Ranking of World Universities26 and the Times Higher Education World University Rankings27.
No data is associated with this article.
Work on this paper was funded by the Templeton World Charity Foundation and was carried out within the project The Epistemic Responsibilities of the University (2016–2019). The opinions expressed in this publication are those of the authors and do not necessarily reflect the views of the Templeton World Charity Foundation.
The funders had no role in study design, data collection and analysis, decision to publish, or preparation of the manuscript.
1Some of us have made this distinction before; see, for instance, Peels R, de Ridder J, Haven T, Bouter L (2019). Value Pluralism in Research Integrity. under review.
2Nosek B et al. (2015). Promoting an Open Research Culture. Science 348 1422–5, https://doi.org/10.1126/science.aab2374 and https://cos.io/our-services/top-guidelines/
3For some of the outcomes, see de Ridder J, Peels R, van Woudenberg R (2018). Scientism: Prospects and Problems (New York: Oxford University Press).
4See National Academies of Sciences, Engineering, and Medicine (2017). Fostering Integrity in Research (Washington, DC: The National Academies Press). https://doi.org/10.17226/21896
5See, e.g., the Singapore Statement (https://wcrif.org/guidance/singapore-statement); ALLEA (2017). The European Code of Conduct for Research Integrity Revised Edition, https://ec.europa.eu/research/participants/data/ref/h2020/other/hi/h2020-ethics_code-of-conduct_en.pdf, last visited May 14th 2019; DORA (2018). San Francisco Declaration on Research Assessment, https://sfdora.org; VSNU (2018). Netherlands Code of Conduct for Research Integrity, Revised Edition, http://www.vsnu.nl/files/documents/Netherlands%20Code%20of%20Conduct%20for%20Research%20Integrity%202018.pdf, last visited May 14th 2019.
6See National Academies of Sciences, Engineering, and Medicine (2017). Fostering Integrity in Research (Washington, DC: The National Academies Press). https://doi.org/10.17226/21896; Hiney, M (2015). Research Integrity: What it Means, Why it Is important and How we Might Protect it. EC Briefing Paper - Research Integrity (https://www.scienceeurope.org/wp-content/uploads/2015/12/Briefing_Paper_Research_Integrity_web.pdf)
7Fanelli, D (2009). How Many Scientists Fabricate and Falsify Research?. PLoS ONE 4(5); e5738. https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0005738 Note that these numbers concern scientists’ self-reporting; they go up considerably when researchers are asked whether they’re aware of colleagues having committed scientific fraud or engaged in questionable research practices.
8KNAW Replication studies (https://www.knaw.nl/nl/actueel/publicaties/replication-studies); Baker, M (2016). Is There a Replicability Crisis? Nature 533(7604): 452–454. https://doi.org/10.1038/533452a Some of us have recently argued that replication is also a desideratum in the humanities. See Peels R and Bouter L (2018). The Possibility and Desirability for Replication in the Humanities. Palgrave Communications 4:95, https://doi.org/10.1057/s41599-018-0149-x.
9Wilkinson MD, Dumontier M, et al. (2016). The FAIR Guiding Principles for Scientific Data Management and Stewardship. Scientific Data 3: 160018. https://doi.org/10.1038/sdata.2016.18; https://www.go-fair.org/fair-principles/
10Nosek B, Ebersole CR, DeHaven AC, Mellor DT (2018). The Preregistration Revolution. PNAS 115: 2600–2606. https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.1708274114
11Moher D, Naudet F, Cristea IA, Miedema F, Ioannidis JPA, and Goodman SN (2018). Assessing Scientists for Hiring, Promotion, and Tenure. PLoS Biol 16(3): e2004089. https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pbio.2004089
12See Battaly H, ed. (2010). Virtue and Vice, Moral and Epistemic (Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell); Baehr J, ed. (2016). Intellectual Virtues and Education: Essays in Applied Virtue Epistemology (New York: Routledge).
13See Ritchhart R (2002). Intellectual Character: What It Is, Why It Matters, and How to Get It (San Francisco: Jossey-Bass).
14See Roberts R and Woods J (2007). Intellectual Virtues (New York: Oxford University Press); Baehr J (2011). The Inquiring Mind (New York: Oxford University Press); Battaly H, ed. (2018). Routledge Handbook of Virtue Epistemology (London: Routledge).
15Berryman S (2016). Ancient Atomism, in: Edward N. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2016/entries/atomism-ancient/.
16See Shea W and Artigas M (2003). Galileo in Rome: The Rise and Fall of a Troublesome Genius (Oxford: Oxford University Press); Remmert V (2005). Galileo, God, and Mathematics. In Koetsier T, Bergmans L (eds.), Mathematics and the Divine. A Historical Study (Amsterdam: Elsevier), pp. 347–360.
19Thus also, Peels R (2018). Epistemic Values in the Humanities and the Sciences, History of Humanities 3.1, 89–111. https://doi.org/10.1086/696304
20See van Woudenberg R (2018). The Nature of the Humanities, Philosophy 93: 109–140. https://doi.org/10.1017/S003181911700047X
21See chapter 2 of Foley R (2018). The Geography of Insight. The Sciences, the Humanities, How They Differ, Why They Matter (Oxford: Oxford University Press).
22See Nussbaum M (2010). Not for Profit: Why Democracy Needs the Humanities (Princeton: Princeton University Press).
23Terwee CB, Prinsen CAC, Chiarotto A, Westerman MJ, Patrick DL, Alonso J, Bouter LM, de Vet HCW, Mokkink LB (2018). COSMIN Methodology for Evaluating the Content Validity of Patient-Reported Outcome Measures: A Delphi Study. Quality of Life Research 27: 1159–70. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11136-018-1829-0
25Ramaswamya V and Ozcan K (2018). What is Co-Creation? An Interactional Creation Framework and its Implications for Value Creation. Journal of Business Research 84: 196–05. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jbusres.2017.11.027
Views | Downloads | |
---|---|---|
F1000Research | - | - |
PubMed Central
Data from PMC are received and updated monthly.
|
- | - |
Is the topic of the opinion article discussed accurately in the context of the current literature?
Partly
Are all factual statements correct and adequately supported by citations?
Partly
Are arguments sufficiently supported by evidence from the published literature?
Partly
Are the conclusions drawn balanced and justified on the basis of the presented arguments?
Yes
Competing Interests: No competing interests were disclosed.
Reviewer Expertise: Molecular biology, molecular genetics, human tissue biobanking, research integrity
Is the topic of the opinion article discussed accurately in the context of the current literature?
Partly
Are all factual statements correct and adequately supported by citations?
Yes
Are arguments sufficiently supported by evidence from the published literature?
Partly
Are the conclusions drawn balanced and justified on the basis of the presented arguments?
Yes
References
1. Rubrics: Useful Assessment Tools. Centre for Teaching Excellence, University of Waterloo. 2019. Reference SourceCompeting Interests: The reviewers are currently engaged in an ongoing debate with the authors of the paper on whether the humanities need a replication drive like that currently ongoing for the sciences. Since the reviewers take the negative side of that debate – we do not think the humanities need a replication drive – and the authors defend the affirmative side, someone might believe we are incapable of offering a fair review. The debate is cordial, however, and one of the authors (Peels) has been included as a presenter in a session conference session on the topic organized by the reviewers. We expect that (fruitful) debate to continue, although it is possible that we could reach consensus on the matter. Although we offer a critical review here, we do so in the spirit of helping the authors strengthen their arguments and not from any ill will.
Alongside their report, reviewers assign a status to the article:
Invited Reviewers | ||
---|---|---|
1 | 2 | |
Version 2 (revision) 06 Jul 20 |
read | |
Version 1 13 Jun 19 |
read | read |
Provide sufficient details of any financial or non-financial competing interests to enable users to assess whether your comments might lead a reasonable person to question your impartiality. Consider the following examples, but note that this is not an exhaustive list:
Sign up for content alerts and receive a weekly or monthly email with all newly published articles
Already registered? Sign in
The email address should be the one you originally registered with F1000.
You registered with F1000 via Google, so we cannot reset your password.
To sign in, please click here.
If you still need help with your Google account password, please click here.
You registered with F1000 via Facebook, so we cannot reset your password.
To sign in, please click here.
If you still need help with your Facebook account password, please click here.
If your email address is registered with us, we will email you instructions to reset your password.
If you think you should have received this email but it has not arrived, please check your spam filters and/or contact for further assistance.
Comments on this article Comments (0)